Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43
You’re reading novel Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43 online at LightNovelFree.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit LightNovelFree.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy!
Now in each of these appet.i.tes, the name "love" is given to the principle of movement towards the end loved. In the natural appet.i.te the principle of this movement is the appet.i.tive subject's connaturalness with the thing to which it tends, and may be called "natural love": thus the connaturalness of a heavy body for the centre, is by reason of its weight and may be called "natural love."
In like manner the apt.i.tude of the sensitive appet.i.te or of the will to some good, that is to say, its very complacency in good is called "sensitive love," or "intellectual" or "rational love." So that sensitive love is in the sensitive appet.i.te, just as intellectual love is in the intellectual appet.i.te. And it belongs to the concupiscible power, because it regards good absolutely, and not under the aspect of difficulty, which is the object of the irascible faculty.
Reply Obj. 1: The words quoted refer to intellectual or rational love.
Reply Obj. 2: Love is spoken of as being fear, joy, desire and sadness, not essentially but causally.
Reply Obj. 3: Natural love is not only in the powers of the vegetal soul, but in all the soul's powers, and also in all the parts of the body, and universally in all things: because, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv), "Beauty and goodness are beloved by all things"; since each single thing has a connaturalness with that which is naturally suitable to it.
________________________
SECOND ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 26, Art. 2]
Whether Love Is a Pa.s.sion?
Objection 1: It would seem that love is not a pa.s.sion. For no power is a pa.s.sion. But every love is a power, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom.
iv). Therefore love is not a pa.s.sion.
Obj. 2: Further, love is a kind of union or bond, as Augustine says (De Trin. viii, 10). But a union or bond is not a pa.s.sion, but rather a relation. Therefore love is not a pa.s.sion.
Obj. 3: Further, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 22) that pa.s.sion is a movement. But love does not imply the movement of the appet.i.te; for this is desire, of which movement love is the principle.
Therefore love is not a pa.s.sion.
_On the contrary,_ The Philosopher says (Ethic. viii, 5) that "love is a pa.s.sion."
_I answer that,_ Pa.s.sion is the effect of the agent on the patient.
Now a natural agent produces a twofold effect on the patient: for in the first place it gives it the form; and secondly it gives it the movement that results from the form. Thus the generator gives the generated body both weight and the movement resulting from weight: so that weight, from being the principle of movement to the place, which is connatural to that body by reason of its weight, can, in a way, be called "natural love." In the same way the appetible object gives the appet.i.te, first, a certain adaptation to itself, which consists in complacency in that object; and from this follows movement towards the appetible object. For "the appet.i.tive movement is circular," as stated in _De Anima_ iii, 10; because the appetible object moves the appet.i.te, introducing itself, as it were, into its intention; while the appet.i.te moves towards the realization of the appetible object, so that the movement ends where it began. Accordingly, the first change wrought in the appet.i.te by the appetible object is called "love," and is nothing else than complacency in that object; and from this complacency results a movement towards that same object, and this movement is "desire"; and lastly, there is rest which is "joy."
Since, therefore, love consists in a change wrought in the appet.i.te by the appetible object, it is evident that love is a pa.s.sion: properly so called, according as it is in the concupiscible faculty; in a wider and extended sense, according as it is in the will.
Reply Obj. 1: Since power denotes a principle of movement or action, Dionysius calls love a power, in so far as it is a principle of movement in the appet.i.te.
Reply Obj. 2: Union belongs to love in so far as by reason of the complacency of the appet.i.te, the lover stands in relation to that which he loves, as though it were himself or part of himself. Hence it is clear that love is not the very relation of union, but that union is a result of love. Hence, too, Dionysius says that "love is a unitive force" (Div. Nom. iv), and the Philosopher says (Polit. ii, 1) that union is the work of love.
Reply Obj. 3: Although love does not denote the movement of the appet.i.te in tending towards the appetible object, yet it denotes that movement whereby the appet.i.te is changed by the appetible object, so as to have complacency therein.
________________________
THIRD ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 26, Art. 3]
Whether Love Is the Same As Dilection?
Objection 1: It would seem that love is the same as dilection. For Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that love is to dilection, "as four is to twice two, and as a rectilinear figure is to one composed of straight lines." But these have the same meaning. Therefore love and dilection denote the same thing.
Obj. 2: Further, the movements of the appet.i.te differ by reason of their objects. But the objects of dilection and love are the same.
Therefore these are the same.
Obj. 3: Further, if dilection and love differ, it seems that it is chiefly in the fact that "dilection refers to good things, love to evil things, as some have maintained," according to Augustine (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7). But they do not differ thus; because as Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7) the holy Scripture uses both words in reference to either good or bad things. Therefore love and dilection do not differ: thus indeed Augustine concludes (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7) that "it is not one thing to speak of love, and another to speak of dilection."
_On the contrary,_ Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "some holy men have held that love means something more G.o.dlike than dilection does."
_I answer that,_ We find four words referring in a way, to the same thing: viz. love, dilection, charity and friends.h.i.+p. They differ, however, in this, that "friends.h.i.+p," according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 5), "is like a habit," whereas "love" and "dilection"
are expressed by way of act or pa.s.sion; and "charity" can be taken either way.
Moreover these three express act in different ways. For love has a wider signification than the others, since every dilection or charity is love, but not vice versa. Because dilection implies, in addition to love, a choice (_electionem_) made beforehand, as the very word denotes: and therefore dilection is not in the concupiscible power, but only in the will, and only in the rational nature. Charity denotes, in addition to love, a certain perfection of love, in so far as that which is loved is held to be of great price, as the word itself implies [*Referring to the Latin "carus" (dear)].
Reply Obj. 1: Dionysius is speaking of love and dilection, in so far as they are in the intellectual appet.i.te; for thus love is the same as dilection.
Reply Obj. 2: The object of love is more general than the object of dilection: because love extends to more than dilection does, as stated above.
Reply Obj. 3: Love and dilection differ, not in respect of good and evil, but as stated. Yet in the intellectual faculty love is the same as dilection. And it is in this sense that Augustine speaks of love in the pa.s.sage quoted: hence a little further on he adds that "a right will is well-directed love, and a wrong will is ill-directed love." However, the fact that love, which is concupiscible pa.s.sion, inclines many to evil, is the reason why some a.s.signed the difference spoken of.
Reply Obj. 4: The reason why some held that, even when applied to the will itself, the word "love" signifies something more G.o.dlike than "dilection," was because love denotes a pa.s.sion, especially in so far as it is in the sensitive appet.i.te; whereas dilection presupposes the judgment of reason. But it is possible for man to tend to G.o.d by love, being as it were pa.s.sively drawn by Him, more than he can possibly be drawn thereto by his reason, which pertains to the nature of dilection, as stated above. And consequently love is more G.o.dlike than dilection.
________________________
FOURTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 26, Art. 4]
Whether Love Is Properly Divided into Love of Friends.h.i.+p and Love of Concupiscence?
Objection 1: It would seem that love is not properly divided into love of friends.h.i.+p and love of concupiscence. For "love is a pa.s.sion, while friends.h.i.+p is a habit," according to the Philosopher (Ethic.
viii, 5). But habit cannot be the member of a division of pa.s.sions.
Therefore love is not properly divided into love of concupiscence and love of friends.h.i.+p.
Obj. 2: Further, a thing cannot be divided by another member of the same division; for man is not a member of the same division as "animal." But concupiscence is a member of the same division as love, as a pa.s.sion distinct from love. Therefore concupiscence is not a division of love.
Obj. 3: Further, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 3) friends.h.i.+p is threefold, that which is founded on _usefulness,_ that which is founded on _pleasure,_ and that which is founded on _goodness._ But useful and pleasant friends.h.i.+p are not without concupiscence. Therefore concupiscence should not be contrasted with friends.h.i.+p.
_On the contrary,_ We are said to love certain things, because we desire them: thus "a man is said to love wine, on account of its sweetness which he desires"; as stated in _Topic._ ii, 3. But we have no friends.h.i.+p for wine and suchlike things, as stated in _Ethic._ viii, 2. Therefore love of concupiscence is distinct from love of friends.h.i.+p.
_I answer that,_ As the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 4), "to love is to wish good to someone." Hence the movement of love has a twofold tendency: towards the good which a man wishes to someone (to himself or to another) and towards that to which he wishes some good.
Accordingly, man has love of concupiscence towards the good that he wishes to another, and love of friends.h.i.+p towards him to whom he wishes good.
Now the members of this division are related as primary and secondary: since that which is loved with the love of friends.h.i.+p is loved simply and for itself; whereas that which is loved with the love of concupiscence, is loved, not simply and for itself, but for something else. For just as that which has existence, is a being simply, while that which exists in another is a relative being; so, because good is convertible with being, the good, which itself has goodness, is good simply; but that which is another's good, is a relative good. Consequently the love with which a thing is loved, that it may have some good, is love simply; while the love, with which a thing is loved, that it may be another's good, is relative love.
Reply Obj. 1: Love is not divided into friends.h.i.+p and concupiscence, but into love of friends.h.i.+p, and love of concupiscence. For a friend is, properly speaking, one to whom we wish good: while we are said to desire, what we wish for ourselves.
Hence the Reply to the Second Objection.
Reply Obj. 3: When friends.h.i.+p is based on usefulness or pleasure, a man does indeed wish his friend some good: and in this respect the character of friends.h.i.+p is preserved. But since he refers this good further to his own pleasure or use, the result is that friends.h.i.+p of the useful or pleasant, in so far as it is connected with love of concupiscence, loses the character to true friends.h.i.+p.
________________________
QUESTION 27
OF THE CAUSE OF LOVE (In Four Articles)
We must now consider the cause of love: and under this head there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether good is the only cause of love?
(2) Whether knowledge is a cause of love?
(3) Whether likeness is a cause of love?
Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43
You're reading novel Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43 online at LightNovelFree.com. You can use the follow function to bookmark your favorite novel ( Only for registered users ). If you find any errors ( broken links, can't load photos, etc.. ), Please let us know so we can fix it as soon as possible. And when you start a conversation or debate about a certain topic with other people, please do not offend them just because you don't like their opinions.
Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43 summary
You're reading Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 43. This novel has been translated by Updating. Author: Saint Aquinas Thomas already has 1045 views.
It's great if you read and follow any novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest, hottest novel everyday and FREE.
LightNovelFree.com is a most smartest website for reading novel online, it can automatic resize images to fit your pc screen, even on your mobile. Experience now by using your smartphone and access to LightNovelFree.com
- Related chapter:
- Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 42
- Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 44