Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93
You’re reading novel Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93 online at LightNovelFree.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit LightNovelFree.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy!
FOURTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 60, Art. 4]
Whether There Are Different Moral Virtues About Different Pa.s.sions?
Objection 1: It would seem that there are not different moral virtues about different pa.s.sions. For there is but one habit about things that concur in their source and end: as is evident especially in the case of sciences. But the pa.s.sions all concur in one source, viz.
love; and they all terminate in the same end, viz. joy or sorrow, as we stated above (Q. 25, AA. 1, 2, 4; Q. 27, A. 4). Therefore there is but one moral virtue about all the pa.s.sions.
Obj. 2: Further, if there were different moral virtues about different pa.s.sions, it would follow that there are as many moral virtues as pa.s.sions. But this clearly is not the case: since there is one moral virtue about contrary pa.s.sions; namely, fort.i.tude, about fear and daring; temperance, about pleasure and sorrow. Therefore there is no need for different moral virtues about different pa.s.sions.
Obj. 3: Further, love, desire, and pleasure are pa.s.sions of different species, as stated above (Q. 23, A. 4). Now there is but one virtue about all these three, viz. temperance. Therefore there are not different moral virtues about different pa.s.sions.
_On the contrary,_ Fort.i.tude is about fear and daring; temperance about desire; meekness about anger; as stated in _Ethic._ iii, 6, 10; iv, 5.
_I answer that,_ It cannot be said that there is only one moral virtue about all the pa.s.sions: since some pa.s.sions are not in the same power as other pa.s.sions; for some belong to the irascible, others to the concupiscible faculty, as stated above (Q. 23, A. 1).
On the other hand, neither does every diversity of pa.s.sions necessarily suffice for a diversity of moral virtues. First, because some pa.s.sions are in contrary opposition to one another, such as joy and sorrow, fear and daring, and so on. About such pa.s.sions as are thus in opposition to one another there must needs be one same virtue. Because, since moral virtue consists in a kind of mean, the mean in contrary pa.s.sions stands in the same ratio to both, even as in the natural order there is but one mean between contraries, e.g.
between black and white. Secondly, because there are different pa.s.sions contradicting reason in the same manner, e.g. by impelling to that which is contrary to reason, or by withdrawing from that which is in accord with reason. Wherefore the different pa.s.sions of the concupiscible faculty do not require different moral virtues, because their movements follow one another in a certain order, as being directed to the one same thing, viz. the attainment of some good or the avoidance of some evil: thus from love proceeds desire, and from desire we arrive at pleasure; and it is the same with the opposite pa.s.sions, for hatred leads to avoidance or dislike, and this leads to sorrow. On the other hand, the irascible pa.s.sions are not all of one order, but are directed to different things: for daring and fear are about some great danger; hope and despair are about some difficult good; while anger seeks to overcome something contrary which has wrought harm. Consequently there are different virtues about such like pa.s.sions: e.g. temperance, about the concupiscible pa.s.sions; fort.i.tude, about fear and daring; magnanimity, about hope and despair; meekness, about anger.
Reply Obj. 1: All the pa.s.sions concur in one common principle and end; but not in one proper principle or end: and so this does not suffice for the unity of moral virtue.
Reply Obj. 2: Just as in the natural order the same principle causes movement from one extreme and movement towards the other; and as in the intellectual order contraries have one common ratio; so too between contrary pa.s.sions there is but one moral virtue, which, like a second nature, consents to reason's dictates.
Reply Obj. 3: Those three pa.s.sions are directed to the same object in a certain order, as stated above: and so they belong to the same virtue.
________________________
FIFTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 60, Art. 5]
Whether the Moral Virtues Differ in Point of the Various Objects of the Pa.s.sions?
Objection 1: It would seem that the moral virtues do not differ according to the objects of the pa.s.sions. For just as there are objects of pa.s.sions, so are there objects of operations. Now those moral virtues that are about operations, do not differ according to the objects of those operations: for the buying and selling either of a house or of a horse belong to the one same virtue of justice.
Therefore neither do those moral virtues that are about pa.s.sions differ according to the objects of those pa.s.sions.
Obj. 2: Further, the pa.s.sions are acts or movements of the sensitive appet.i.te. Now it needs a greater difference to differentiate habits than acts. Hence diverse objects which do not diversify the species of pa.s.sions, do not diversify the species of moral virtue: so that there is but one moral virtue about all objects of pleasure, and the same applies to the other pa.s.sions.
Obj. 3: Further, more or less do not change a species. Now various objects of pleasure differ only by reason of being more or less pleasurable. Therefore all objects of pleasure belong to one species of virtue: and for the same reason so do all fearful objects, and the same applies to others. Therefore moral virtue is not diversified according to the objects of the pa.s.sions.
Obj. 4: Further, virtue hinders evil, even as it produces good. But there are various virtues about the desires for good things: thus temperance is about desires for the pleasure of touch, and _eutrapelia_ about pleasures in games. Therefore there should be different virtues about fears of evils.
_On the contrary,_ Chast.i.ty is about s.e.xual pleasures, abstinence about pleasures of the table, and _eutrapelia_ about pleasures in games.
_I answer that,_ The perfection of a virtue depends on the reason; whereas the perfection of a pa.s.sion depends on the sensitive appet.i.te. Consequently virtues must needs be differentiated according to their relation to reason, but the pa.s.sions according to their relation to the appet.i.te. Hence the objects of the pa.s.sions, according as they are variously related to the sensitive appet.i.te, cause the different species of pa.s.sions: while, according as they are related to reason, they cause the different species of virtues. Now the movement of reason is not the same as that of the sensitive appet.i.te. Wherefore nothing hinders a difference of objects from causing diversity of pa.s.sions, without causing diversity of virtues, as when one virtue is about several pa.s.sions, as stated above (A. 4); and again, a difference of objects from causing different virtues, without causing a difference of pa.s.sions, since several virtues are directed about one pa.s.sion, e.g. pleasure.
And because diverse pa.s.sions belonging to diverse powers, always belong to diverse virtues, as stated above (A. 4); therefore a difference of objects that corresponds to a difference of powers always causes a specific difference of virtues--for instance the difference between that which is good absolutely speaking, and that which is good and difficult to obtain. Moreover since the reason rules man's lower powers in a certain order, and even extends to outward things; hence, one single object of the pa.s.sions, according as it is apprehended by sense, imagination, or reason, and again, according as it belongs to the soul, body, or external things, has various relations to reason, and consequently is of a nature to cause a difference of virtues. Consequently man's good which is the object of love, desire and pleasure, may be taken as referred either to a bodily sense, or to the inner apprehension of the mind: and this same good may be directed to man's good in himself, either in his body or in his soul, or to man's good in relation to other men. And every such difference, being differently related to reason, differentiates virtues.
Accordingly, if we take a good, and it be something discerned by the sense of touch, and something pertaining to the upkeep of human life either in the individual or in the species, such as the pleasures of the table or of s.e.xual intercourse, it will belong to the virtue of _temperance._ As regards the pleasures of the other senses, they are not intense, and so do not present much difficulty to the reason: hence there is no virtue corresponding to them; for virtue, "like art, is about difficult things" (Ethic. ii, 3).
On the other hand, good discerned not by the senses, but by an inner power, and belonging to man in himself, is like money and honor; the former, by its very nature, being employable for the good of the body, while the latter is based on the apprehension of the mind.
These goods again may be considered either absolutely, in which way they concern the concupiscible faculty, or as being difficult to obtain, in which way they belong to the irascible part: which distinction, however, has no place in pleasurable objects of touch; since such are of base condition, and are becoming to man in so far as he has something in common with irrational animals. Accordingly in reference to money considered as a good absolutely, as an object of desire, pleasure, or love, there is _liberality_: but if we consider this good as difficult to get, and as being the object of our hope, there is _magnificence_ [*_megaloprepeia_]. With regard to that good which we call honor, taken absolutely, as the object of love, we have a virtue called _philotimia,_ i.e. _love of honor_: while if we consider it as hard to attain, and as an object of hope, then we have _magnanimity._ Wherefore liberality and _philotimia_ seem to be in the concupiscible part, while magnificence and magnanimity are in the irascible.
As regards man's good in relation to other men, it does not seem hard to obtain, but is considered absolutely, as the object of the concupiscible pa.s.sions. This good may be pleasurable to a man in his behavior towards another either in some serious matter, in actions, to wit, that are directed by reason to a due end, or in playful actions, viz. that are done for mere pleasure, and which do not stand in the same relation to reason as the former. Now one man behaves towards another in serious matters, in two ways. First, as being pleasant in his regard, by becoming speech and deeds: and this belongs to a virtue which Aristotle (Ethic. ii, 7) calls "friends.h.i.+p"
[*_philia_], and may be rendered "affability." Secondly, one man behaves towards another by being frank with him, in words and deeds: this belongs to another virtue which (Ethic. iv, 7) he calls "truthfulness" [*_aletheia_]. For frankness is more akin to the reason than pleasure, and serious matters than play. Hence there is another virtue about the pleasures of games, which the Philosopher calls _eutrapelia_ (Ethic. iv, 8).
It is therefore evident that, according to Aristotle, there are ten moral virtues about the pa.s.sions, viz. fort.i.tude, temperance, liberality, magnificence, magnanimity, _philotimia,_ gentleness, friends.h.i.+p, truthfulness, and _eutrapelia,_ all of which differ in respect of their diverse matter, pa.s.sions, or objects: so that if we add _justice,_ which is about operations, there will be eleven in all.
Reply Obj. 1: All objects of the same specific operation have the same relation to reason: not so all the objects of the same specific pa.s.sion; because operations do not thwart reason as the pa.s.sions do.
Reply Obj. 2: Pa.s.sions are not differentiated by the same rule as virtues are, as stated above.
Reply Obj. 3: More and less do not cause a difference of species, unless they bear different relations to reason.
Reply Obj. 4: Good is a more potent mover than evil: because evil does not cause movement save in virtue of good, as Dionysius states (Div. Nom. iv). Hence an evil does not prove an obstacle to reason, so as to require virtues unless that evil be great; there being, seemingly, one such evil corresponding to each kind of pa.s.sion. Hence there is but one virtue, meekness, for every form of anger; and, again, but one virtue, fort.i.tude, for all forms of daring. On the other hand, good involves difficulty, which requires virtue, even if it be not a great good in that particular kind of pa.s.sion.
Consequently there are various moral virtues about desires, as stated above.
________________________
QUESTION 61
OF THE CARDINAL VIRTUES (In Five Articles)
We must now consider the cardinal virtues: under which head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the moral virtues should be called cardinal or princ.i.p.al virtues?
(2) Of their number;
(3) Which are they?
(4) Whether they differ from one another?
(5) Whether they are fittingly divided into social, perfecting, perfect, and exemplar virtues?
________________________
FIRST ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 61, Art. 1]
Whether the Moral Virtues Should Be Called Cardinal or Princ.i.p.al Virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that moral virtues should not be called cardinal or princ.i.p.al virtues. For "the opposite members of a division are by nature simultaneous" (Categor. x), so that one is not princ.i.p.al rather than another. Now all the virtues are opposite members of the division of the genus "virtue." Therefore none of them should be called princ.i.p.al.
Obj. 2: Further, the end is princ.i.p.al as compared to the means. But the theological virtues are about the end; while the moral virtues are about the means. Therefore the theological virtues, rather than the moral virtues, should be called princ.i.p.al or cardinal.
Obj. 3: Further, that which is essentially so is princ.i.p.al in comparison with that which is so by partic.i.p.ation. But the intellectual virtues belong to that which is essentially rational: whereas the moral virtues belong to that which is rational by partic.i.p.ation, as stated above (Q. 58, A. 3). Therefore the intellectual virtues are princ.i.p.al, rather than the moral virtues.
_On the contrary,_ Ambrose in explaining the words, "Blessed are the poor in spirit" (Luke 6:20) says: "We know that there are four cardinal virtues, viz. temperance, justice, prudence, and fort.i.tude."
But these are moral virtues. Therefore the moral virtues are cardinal virtues.
_I answer that,_ When we speak of virtue simply, we are understood to speak of human virtue. Now human virtue, as stated above (Q. 56, A.
3), is one that answers to the perfect idea of virtue, which requires rect.i.tude of the appet.i.te: for such like virtue not only confers the faculty of doing well, but also causes the good deed done. On the other hand, the name virtue is applied to one that answers imperfectly to the idea of virtue, and does not require rect.i.tude of the appet.i.te: because it merely confers the faculty of doing well without causing the good deed to be done. Now it is evident that the perfect is princ.i.p.al as compared to the imperfect: and so those virtues which imply rect.i.tude of the appet.i.te are called princ.i.p.al virtues. Such are the moral virtues, and prudence alone, of the intellectual virtues, for it is also something of a moral virtue, as was clearly shown above (Q. 57, A. 4). Consequently, those virtues which are called princ.i.p.al or cardinal are fittingly placed among the moral virtues.
Reply Obj. 1: When a univocal genus is divided into its species, the members of the division are on a par in the point of the generic idea; although considered in their nature as things, one species may surpa.s.s another in rank and perfection, as man in respect of other animals. But when we divide an a.n.a.logous term, which is applied to several things, but to one before it is applied to another, nothing hinders one from ranking before another, even in the point of the generic idea; as the notion of being is applied to substance princ.i.p.ally in relation to accident. Such is the division of virtue into various kinds of virtue: since the good defined by reason is not found in the same way in all things.
Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93
You're reading novel Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93 online at LightNovelFree.com. You can use the follow function to bookmark your favorite novel ( Only for registered users ). If you find any errors ( broken links, can't load photos, etc.. ), Please let us know so we can fix it as soon as possible. And when you start a conversation or debate about a certain topic with other people, please do not offend them just because you don't like their opinions.
Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93 summary
You're reading Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 93. This novel has been translated by Updating. Author: Saint Aquinas Thomas already has 1108 views.
It's great if you read and follow any novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest, hottest novel everyday and FREE.
LightNovelFree.com is a most smartest website for reading novel online, it can automatic resize images to fit your pc screen, even on your mobile. Experience now by using your smartphone and access to LightNovelFree.com
- Related chapter:
- Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 92
- Summa Theologica Part II (Pars Prima Secundae) Part 94