Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63
You’re reading novel Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63 online at LightNovelFree.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit LightNovelFree.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy!
Others, therefore, considering this ident.i.ty, said that the properties were indeed the persons; but not "in" the persons; for, they said, there are no properties in G.o.d except in our way of speaking, as stated above (Q. 32, A. 2). We must, however, say that there are properties in G.o.d; as we have shown (Q. 32, A. 2). These are designated by abstract terms, being forms, as it were, of the persons.
So, since the nature of a form requires it to be "in" that of which it is the form, we must say that the properties are in the persons, and yet that they are the persons; as we say that the essence is in G.o.d, and yet is G.o.d.
Reply Obj. 1: Person and property are really the same, but differ in concept. Consequently, it does not follow that if one is multiplied, the other must also be multiplied. We must, however, consider that in G.o.d, by reason of the divine simplicity, a twofold real ident.i.ty exists as regards what in creatures are distinct. For, since the divine simplicity excludes the composition of matter and form, it follows that in G.o.d the abstract is the same as the concrete, as "G.o.dhead" and "G.o.d." And as the divine simplicity excludes the composition of subject and accident, it follows that whatever is attributed to G.o.d, is His essence Itself; and so, wisdom and power are the same in G.o.d, because they are both in the divine essence.
According to this twofold ident.i.ty, property in G.o.d is the same as person. For personal properties are the same as the persons because the abstract and the concrete are the same in G.o.d; since they are the subsisting persons themselves, as paternity is the Father Himself, and filiation is the Son, and procession is the Holy Ghost. But the non-personal properties are the same as the persons according to the other reason of ident.i.ty, whereby whatever is attributed to G.o.d is His own essence. Thus, common spiration is the same as the person of the Father, and the person of the Son; not that it is one self-subsisting person; but that as there is one essence in the two persons, so also there is one property in the two persons, as above explained (Q. 30, A. 2).
Reply Obj. 2: The properties are said to be in the essence, only by mode of ident.i.ty; but in the persons they exist by mode of ident.i.ty, not merely in reality, but also in the mode of signification; as the form exists in its subject. Thus the properties determine and distinguish the persons, but not the essence.
Reply Obj. 3: Notional participles and verbs signify the notional acts: and acts belong to a _suppositum._ Now, properties are not designated as _supposita,_ but as forms of _supposita._ And so their mode of signification is against notional participles and verbs being predicated of the properties.
_______________________
SECOND ARTICLE [I, Q. 40, Art. 2]
Whether the Persons Are Distinguished by the Relations?
Objection 1: It would seem that the persons are not distinguished by the relations. For simple things are distinct by themselves. But the persons are supremely simple. Therefore they are distinguished by themselves, and not by the relation.
Obj. 2: Further, a form is distinguished only in relation to its genus. For white is distinguished from black only by quality. But "hypostasis" signifies an individual in the genus of substance.
Therefore the hypostases cannot be distinguished by relations.
Obj. 3: Further, what is absolute comes before what is relative. But the distinction of the divine persons is the primary distinction.
Therefore the divine persons are not distinguished by the relations.
Obj. 4: Further, whatever presupposes distinction cannot be the first principle of distinction. But relation presupposes distinction, which comes into its definition; for a relation is essentially what is towards another. Therefore the first distinctive principle in G.o.d cannot be relation.
_On the contrary,_ Boethius says (De Trin.): "Relation alone multiplies the Trinity of the divine persons."
_I answer that,_ In whatever mult.i.tude of things is to be found something common to all, it is necessary to seek out the principle of distinction. So, as the three persons agree in the unity of essence, we must seek to know the principle of distinction whereby they are several. Now, there are two principles of difference between the divine persons, and these are "origin" and "relation." Although these do not really differ, yet they differ in the mode of signification; for "origin" is signified by way of act, as "generation"; and "relation" by way of the form, as "paternity."
Some, then, considering that relation follows upon act, have said that the divine hypostases are distinguished by origin, so that we may say that the Father is distinguished from the Son, inasmuch as the former begets and the latter is begotten. Further, that the relations, or the properties, make known the distinctions of the hypostases or persons as resulting therefrom; as also in creatures the properties manifest the distinctions of individuals, which distinctions are caused by the material principles.
This opinion, however, cannot stand--for two reasons. Firstly, because, in order that two things be understood as distinct, their distinction must be understood as resulting from something intrinsic to both; thus in things created it results from their matter or their form. Now origin of a thing does not designate anything intrinsic, but means the way from something, or to something; as generation signifies the way to a thing generated, and as proceeding from the generator.
Hence it is not possible that what is generated and the generator should be distinguished by generation alone; but in the generator and in the thing generated we must presuppose whatever makes them to be distinguished from each other. In a divine person there is nothing to presuppose but essence, and relation or property. Whence, since the persons agree in essence, it only remains to be said that the persons are distinguished from each other by the relations. Secondly: because the distinction of the divine persons is not to be so understood as if what is common to them all is divided, because the common essence remains undivided; but the distinguis.h.i.+ng principles themselves must const.i.tute the things which are distinct. Now the relations or the properties distinguish or const.i.tute the hypostases or persons, inasmuch as they are themselves the subsisting persons; as paternity is the Father, and filiation is the Son, because in G.o.d the abstract and the concrete do not differ. But it is against the nature of origin that it should const.i.tute hypostasis or person. For origin taken in an active sense signifies proceeding from a subsisting person, so that it presupposes the latter; while in a pa.s.sive sense origin, as "nativity," signifies the way to a subsisting person, and as not yet const.i.tuting the person.
It is therefore better to say that the persons or hypostases are distinguished rather by relations than by origin. For, although in both ways they are distinguished, nevertheless in our mode of understanding they are distinguished chiefly and firstly by relations; whence this name "Father" signifies not only a property, but also the hypostasis; whereas this term "Begetter" or "Begetting" signifies property only; forasmuch as this name "Father" signifies the relation which is distinctive and const.i.tutive of the hypostasis; and this term "Begetter" or "Begotten" signifies the origin which is not distinctive and const.i.tutive of the hypostasis.
Reply Obj. 1: The persons are the subsisting relations themselves.
Hence it is not against the simplicity of the divine persons for them to be distinguished by the relations.
Reply Obj. 2: The divine persons are not distinguished as regards being, in which they subsist, nor in anything absolute, but only as regards something relative. Hence relation suffices for their distinction.
Reply Obj. 3: The more prior a distinction is, the nearer it approaches to unity; and so it must be the least possible distinction. So the distinction of the persons must be by that which distinguishes the least possible; and this is by relation.
Reply Obj. 4: Relation presupposes the distinction of the subjects, when it is an accident; but when the relation is subsistent, it does not presuppose, but brings about distinction. For when it is said that relation is by nature to be towards another, the word "another"
signifies the correlative which is not prior, but simultaneous in the order of nature.
_______________________
THIRD ARTICLE [I, Q. 40, Art. 3]
Whether the Hypostases Remain If the Relations Are Mentally Abstracted from the Persons?
Objection 1: It would seem that the hypostases remain if the properties or relations are mentally abstracted from the persons. For that to which something is added, may be understood when the addition is taken away; as man is something added to animal which can be understood if rational be taken away. But person is something added to hypostasis; for person is "a hypostasis distinguished by a property of dignity." Therefore, if a personal property be taken away from a person, the hypostasis remains.
Obj. 2: Further, that the Father is Father, and that He is someone, are not due to the same reason. For as He is the Father by paternity, supposing He is some one by paternity, it would follow that the Son, in Whom there is not paternity, would not be "someone." So when paternity is mentally abstracted from the Father, He still remains "someone"--that is, a hypostasis. Therefore, if property be removed from person, the hypostasis remains.
Obj. 3: Further, Augustine says (De Trin. v, 6): "Unbegotten is not the same as Father; for if the Father had not begotten the Son, nothing would prevent Him being called unbegotten." But if He had not begotten the Son, there would be no paternity in Him. Therefore, if paternity be removed, there still remains the hypostasis of the Father as unbegotten.
_On the contrary,_ Hilary says (De Trin. iv): "The Son has nothing else than birth." But He is Son by "birth." Therefore, if filiation be removed, the Son's hypostasis no more remains; and the same holds as regards the other persons.
_I answer that,_ Abstraction by the intellect is twofold--when the universal is abstracted from the particular, as animal abstracted from man; and when the form is abstracted from the matter, as the form of a circle is abstracted by the intellect from any sensible matter. The difference between these two abstractions consists in the fact that in the abstraction of the universal from the particular, that from which the abstraction is made does not remain; for when the difference of rationality is removed from man, the man no longer remains in the intellect, but animal alone remains. But in the abstraction of the form from the matter, both the form and the matter remain in the intellect; as, for instance, if we abstract the form of a circle from bra.s.s, there remains in our intellect separately the understanding both of a circle, and of bra.s.s. Now, although there is no universal nor particular in G.o.d, nor form and matter, in reality; nevertheless, as regards the mode of signification there is a certain likeness of these things in G.o.d; and thus Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 6) that "substance is common and hypostasis is particular." So, if we speak of the abstraction of the universal from the particular, the common universal essence remains in the intellect if the properties are removed; but not the hypostasis of the Father, which is, as it were, a particular.
But as regards the abstraction of the form from the matter, if the non-personal properties are removed, then the idea of the hypostases and persons remains; as, for instance, if the fact of the Father's being unbegotten or spirating be mentally abstracted from the Father, the Father's hypostasis or person remains.
If, however, the personal property be mentally abstracted, the idea of the hypostasis no longer remains. For the personal properties are not to be understood as added to the divine hypostases, as a form is added to a pre-existing subject: but they carry with them their own _supposita,_ inasmuch as they are themselves subsisting persons; thus paternity is the Father Himself. For hypostasis signifies something distinct in G.o.d, since hypostasis means an individual substance. So, as relation distinguishes and const.i.tutes the hypostases, as above explained (A. 2), it follows that if the personal relations are mentally abstracted, the hypostases no longer remain. Some, however, think, as above noted, that the divine hypostases are not distinguished by the relations, but only by origin; so that the Father is a hypostasis as not from another, and the Son is a hypostasis as from another by generation. And that the consequent relations which are to be regarded as properties of dignity, const.i.tute the notion of a person, and are thus called "personal properties." Hence, if these relations are mentally abstracted, the hypostasis, but not the persons, remain.
But this is impossible, for two reasons: first, because the relations distinguish and const.i.tute the hypostases, as shown above (A. 2); secondly, because every hypostasis of a rational nature is a person, as appears from the definition of Boethius (De Duab. Nat.) that, "person is the individual substance of a rational nature." Hence, to have hypostasis and not person, it would be necessary to abstract the rationality from the nature, but not the property from the person.
Reply Obj. 1: Person does not add to hypostasis a distinguis.h.i.+ng property absolutely, but a distinguis.h.i.+ng property of dignity, all of which must be taken as the difference. Now, this distinguis.h.i.+ng property is one of dignity precisely because it is understood as subsisting in a rational nature. Hence, if the distinguis.h.i.+ng property be removed from the person, the hypostasis no longer remains; whereas it would remain were the rationality of the nature removed; for both person and hypostasis are individual substances.
Consequently, in G.o.d the distinguis.h.i.+ng relation belongs essentially to both.
Reply Obj. 2: By paternity the Father is not only Father, but is a person, and is "someone," or a hypostasis. It does not follow, however, that the Son is not "someone" or a hypostasis; just as it does not follow that He is not a person.
Reply Obj. 3: Augustine does not mean to say that the hypostasis of the Father would remain as unbegotten, if His paternity were removed, as if innascibility const.i.tuted and distinguished the hypostasis of the Father; for this would be impossible, since "being unbegotten"
says nothing positive and is only a negation, as he himself says. But he speaks in a general sense, forasmuch as not every unbegotten being is the Father. So, if paternity be removed, the hypostasis of the Father does not remain in G.o.d, as distinguished from the other persons, but only as distinguished from creatures; as the Jews understand it.
_______________________
FOURTH ARTICLE [I, Q. 40, Art. 4]
Whether the properties presuppose the notional acts?
Objection 1: It would seem that the notional acts are understood before the properties. For the Master of the Sentences says (Sent. i, D, xxvii) that "the Father always is, because He is ever begetting the Son." So it seems that generation precedes paternity in the order of intelligence.
Obj. 2: Further, in the order of intelligence every relation presupposes that on which it is founded; as equality presupposes quant.i.ty. But paternity is a relation founded on the action of generation. Therefore paternity presupposes generation.
Obj. 3: Further, active generation is to paternity as nativity is to filiation. But filiation presupposes nativity; for the Son is so called because He is born. Therefore paternity also presupposes generation.
_On the contrary,_ Generation is the operation of the person of the Father. But paternity const.i.tutes the person of the Father. Therefore in the order of intelligence, paternity is prior to generation.
_I answer that,_ According to the opinion that the properties do not distinguish and const.i.tute the hypostases in G.o.d, but only manifest them as already distinct and const.i.tuted, we must absolutely say that the relations in our mode of understanding follow upon the notional acts, so that we can say, without qualifying the phrase, that "because He begets, He is the Father." A distinction, however, is needed if we suppose that the relations distinguish and const.i.tute the divine hypostases. For origin has in G.o.d an active and pa.s.sive signification--active, as generation is attributed to the Father, and spiration, taken for the notional act, is attributed to the Father and the Son; pa.s.sive, as nativity is attributed to the Son, and procession to the Holy Ghost. For, in the order of intelligence, origin, in the pa.s.sive sense, simply precedes the personal properties of the person proceeding; because origin, as pa.s.sively understood, signifies the way to a person const.i.tuted by the property. Likewise, origin signified actively is prior in the order of intelligence to the non-personal relation of the person originating; as the notional act of spiration precedes, in the order of intelligence, the unnamed relative property common to the Father and the Son. The personal property of the Father can be considered in a twofold sense: firstly, as a relation; and thus again in the order of intelligence it presupposes the notional act, for relation, as such, is founded upon an act: secondly, according as it const.i.tutes the person; and thus the notional act presupposes the relation, as an action presupposes a person acting.
Reply Obj. 1: When the Master says that "because He begets, He is Father," the term "Father" is taken as meaning relation only, but not as signifying the subsisting person; for then it would be necessary to say conversely that because He is Father He begets.
Reply Obj. 2: This objection avails of paternity as a relation, but not as const.i.tuting a person.
Reply Obj. 3: Nativity is the way to the person of the Son; and so, in the order of intelligence, it precedes filiation, even as const.i.tuting the person of the Son. But active generation signifies a proceeding from the person of the Father; wherefore it presupposes the personal property of the Father.
_______________________
QUESTION 41
OF THE PERSONS IN REFERENCE TO THE NOTIONAL ACTS (In Six Articles)
Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63
You're reading novel Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63 online at LightNovelFree.com. You can use the follow function to bookmark your favorite novel ( Only for registered users ). If you find any errors ( broken links, can't load photos, etc.. ), Please let us know so we can fix it as soon as possible. And when you start a conversation or debate about a certain topic with other people, please do not offend them just because you don't like their opinions.
Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63 summary
You're reading Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 63. This novel has been translated by Updating. Author: Saint Aquinas Thomas already has 1112 views.
It's great if you read and follow any novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest, hottest novel everyday and FREE.
LightNovelFree.com is a most smartest website for reading novel online, it can automatic resize images to fit your pc screen, even on your mobile. Experience now by using your smartphone and access to LightNovelFree.com
- Related chapter:
- Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 62
- Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 64